The Papal Encyclical and Collective Action

As Pope Francis begins his first visit to the United States it seemed appropriate to reflect on the leadership his Holiness has shown since becoming pontiff. While I am not Catholic myself – though many in my family are – it seems reasonable as a person in the world to give some attention to the spiritual leader of 1.2 billion people worldwide.

Some time ago, I had the opportunity to read and reflect on Pope Francis’ encyclical on the environment, which was released back in June. For those who aren’t familiar with the term, a Papal encyclical is essentially a formal letter on Catholic doctrine sent sent by the pope to the to bishops.

The encyclical drew attention for its strong words of environmentalism: “…Our common home is like a sister…This sister now cries out to us because of the harm we have inflicted on her by our irresponsible use and abuse of the goods with which God has endowed her. We have come to see ourselves as her lords and masters, entitled to plunder her at will.”

Personally, I was more intrigued by his civic message: “I urgently appeal, then, for a new dialogue about how we are shaping the future of our planet. We need a conversation which includes everyone, since the environmental challenge we are undergoing, and its human roots, concern and affect us all.”

He thanks those who are taking action and stresses the urgency of further action, but at its core, his message is a call for dialogue. Importantly, he doesn’t offer a specific policy prescription, he doesn’t tell us what to do – he tells us the tool we should use to figure it out.

Some have criticized this approach – if the Pope has the ability to galvanize billions of people, should he not urge them focus their collective energies on a concrete, meaningful, and impactful goal?

In someways, this question mirrors a common debate of community organizing. The most effective way to address a concert problem in a community is generally not the most egalitarian. But developing the leadership of all people equally is better for a community in the long run. Miles Horton describes this tension eloquently:

If you’re into having a successful organizing campaign and dealing with a specific project, and that’s the goal, then whether you do it yourself or an expert does it or some bountiful person in the community does it, or the government does it without your involvement because that solves the problem—then you don’t take the time to let people develop their own solutions. If the purpose is to solve the problem, there are a lot of ways to solve the problem that are so much simpler than going through all this educational process…But if education is to be part of the process, then you may not actually get that problem solved, but you’ve educated a lot of people. You have to make that choice.

I suppose the Pope could just give us answers. He could be the expert and tell us what to do the way that politicians, businessmen, and other technocrats tell us what to do. In a lot of ways it’s easier when someone tells us what to do – we can judge the advice by our opinion of the person giving it, but we don’t have to work out any hard problems ourselves. We can leave that to the experts and the people in charge.

I find it very powerful that Pope Francis chose not to go this route. Because he isn’t a politician or businessman, or some other technocratic expert. He is a spiritual leader. Education is his goal. Supporting the positive development of diverse people across the globe is his goal.

So, no, he won’t tell us what to do. But he will urge us, strongly and in no uncertain terms to find it within ourselves to act.

We are leaders. Our thoughts and voices and actions are needed. Each of us has something to contribute and we all must work together if we are to ever hope of addressing the intractable problems of our day.

facebooktwittergoogle_plusredditlinkedintumblrmail

Common Wealth Trusts as an Answer to Enclosure

Peter Barnes, an old colleague of mine who writes about the commons from an economic perspective, recently published an essay about “common wealth trusts” as a structure to be used in transitioning to a new economy.  The essay, on the Great Transition Initiative website, recapitulates and extends an idea that Barnes has written about in the past – how to use stakeholder trusts to manage common assets (minerals, forests, electromagnetic spectrum, groundwater, etc.) while providing dividends to all citizens who are also co-owners of those assets. 

Barnes argues that common wealth trusts “address the two greatest flaws in contemporary capitalism—its relentless destruction of nature and widening of inequality—while still keeping the benefits that markets provide.”  Trusts can work because they can provide clear (collective) property rights and formal management systems around resources that are invisible to markets and in many instances threatened with privatization.  He writes:

…..Markets currently do not acknowledge such wealth or recognize its value, much less its common ownership. Because of this enormous market failure, private businesses take, use, or pollute common wealth without limit, generally without paying its right­ful owners for the pri­vi­lege. By so doing, private businesses and their narrow group of owners capture much of the value added by common wealth, exacerbating inequality. If businesses had to pay for the use of common wealth, these things would not happen, or at least would happen much less. What are now unpriced exter­nal­i­ties or straight-out thefts would become costs for businesses that could generate income for everyone.

“Organizing common wealth so that markets respect its co-inheritors and co-beneficiaries requires the creation of common wealth trusts, legally accountable to future generations,” Barnes argues. “These trusts would have authority to limit usage of threatened ecosystems, charge for the use of public resources, and pay per capita dividends. Designing and creating a suite of such trusts would counterbalance profit-seeking activity, slow the destruction of nature, and reduce inequality.”

read more

qualms about Effective Altruism

Effective Altruism is a growing movement that will surely make some valuable contributions. But I have my doubts about its main direction.

This is a prominent summary from the Effective Altruism website:

If you are reading this, you are in an extraordinary position. 

It has never been more possible for you to have a meaningful, positive impact on a massive scale. With the rise of evidence-driven interventions, we each have an unprecedented opportunity to save lives and prevent unnecessary suffering.

Effective Altruism is a growing social movement that combines both the heart and the head: compassion guided by data and reason. It’s about dedicating a significant part of one’s life to improving the world and rigorously asking the question, “Of all the possible ways to make a difference, how can I make the greatest difference?”

Here is one interpretation of the movement: It is about guiding the allocation of discretionary assets (mainly, charitable contributions) to improve other people’s welfare, which is measured in utilitarian terms. Utilitarians disagree about the appropriate proxy measure of welfare (subjective happiness, preference-satisfaction, purchasing-power, Disability-Adjusted Life-Years, etc.), but Effective Altruists can sidestep that debate by focusing–appropriately–on the world’s poorest people, who score low on all those measures.

My objections to this version of Effective Altruism:

  1. Discretionary philanthropic decisions aren’t very consequential. Americans give about 2% of disposable income to charity. Our choices as voters, political activists, investors, and consumers are hugely more important than our decisions about where to give money.
  2. Effective Altruism seems to be about a donor affecting other people. (“How can I make the greatest difference [to them]?”) But in making unilateral decisions, even with the best intentions, I am exercising power over fellow human beings. I am deciding what counts as a good end for them and good means to that end. I am also influencing their longer-term capacity to make decisions themselves. I could help them with that–for instance, by subsidizing the education of young girls in poor countries, I might boost their voice and political agency. But I could also undermine their capacity for self-government while assisting them in an immediate, material way. For instance, I could build dependence and reduce autonomy. In Self Reliance, Emerson says about his own charity, “Though I confess with shame I sometimes succumb and give the dollar, it is a wicked dollar which by and by I shall have the manhood to withhold.” Emerson took the argument far further than I would, but there was truth in it.
  3. The definition of altruism seems to be that person A will try to improve the situation of persons B, C, and D without regard to A’s interests. But social improvement typically comes from people acting in their own interest, albeit effectively and wisely–with an eye to the longer term and a broad definition of interests. I am highly skeptical of any large-scale social strategy that relies upon altruism, especially since the only people in a position to be effectively altruistic at large scales are the ones with a lot of resources. At best, I doubt they have enough leverage. At worst, I don’t trust them to work in other people’s interests. Witness the arguments by some Effective Altruists that we ought to protect humanity against asteroid strikes. That sounds like a fun way for a tech. billionaire to allocate tax-deductible charitable contributions, but not exactly what the world’s poorest people would ask for.

An Effective Altruist can acknowledge all those criticisms and respond that the movement is not just about the allocation of discretionary philanthropic resources. If, for instance, the best way to improve lives is to enhance the political agency of poor girls in developing countries, that’s what the Effective Altruist should invest in. If a US citizen can do more good by supporting a given political campaign than by giving money overseas, then the former is the right choice. And if a donation would create a relation of dependency, the Effective Altruist can refrain from spending money that way.

In short, I have accused Effective Altruists of ignoring politics and power, but they can reply that their analysis should (or does) include just these issues.

My objections to that broader version of Effective Altruism:

  1. It doesn’t seem original in the way implied by its slogans: e.g., “It has never been more possible for you to have a meaningful, positive impact on a massive scale.” If questions of governance, politics, power, agency, and culture are also relevant, then we have been debating how to have a “positive impact” at large scales for two millennia. I believe that we know less about 21st century political-economic systems and how to change them than we knew about the issues that faced industrialized nation-states in 1950. For instance, there may be no more important question today than how to reduce endemic corruption without resorting to authoritarianism. I don’t believe there are any “evidence-driven interventions” for that problem.
  2. If power and agency matter, then decisions ought to be made by groups that include the poor as well as the rich, and that requires a different set of ideas and skills than the ones that Effective Altruism offers. I say that the right question is not “How can I make the greatest difference?” but “What should we do?” An Effective Altruist could reply that what I should do is always fundamental, because I have to decide what groups to join and how to interact within them. For instance, in a deliberation, what arguments should I personally offer–and to whom–and what responses should I find persuasive? I agree, to a point, that my choices are a primary concern for me. Yet Effective Altruism puts the focus on the wrong intellectual skills. It is all about means/ends rationality to guide individual choice: what are the consequences of my actions? If instead we ask, “What should we do?” then we need skills of listening, interpretation, diplomacy, responsible persuasion, and inspirational leadership.
  3. This version of Effective Altruism still seems vulnerable to the critique J.S. Mill leveled against the early British Utilitarians: it overlooks the cultivation of the inner life. The classical utilitarians had defined the goal of life as happiness and had argued that a society could maximize the happiness of its members by getting its laws right. Mill grew up in that milieu, as the son of a great classical utilitarian. As a young man, he became deeply depressed. He asked himself:

“Suppose that all your objects in life were realized; that all the changes in institutions and opinions which you are looking forward to, could be completely effected at this very instant: would this be a great joy and happiness to you?” And an irrepressible self-consciousness distinctly answered, “No!” At this my heart sank within me: the whole foundation on which my life was constructed fell down. All my happiness was to have been found in the continual pursuit of this end. The end had ceased to charm, and how could there ever again be any interest in the means? I seemed to have nothing left to live for.

I elaborate Mill’s point as follows: it seems to be necessary for human beings to be involved in making themselves happy or satisfied; no one can simply do that for us. Some people who know no physical pain and have plenty of money are nevertheless miserable to the point of suicide. Poor villagers who live under a repressive government can be happier than wealthy suburbanites who are well treated by the state. Even if the goal were to maximize everyone’s happiness, that couldn’t be accomplished by a world of individuals who were concerned only with others. They would also have to be responsible for themselves. Pure altruism or other-regardingness is not the ideal, because there would then be no one in a position to make each individual happier.

Mill’s ultimate response was to reemphasize the inner life. “The important change which my opinions at this time underwent, was that I, for the first time, gave its proper place, among the prime necessities of human well-being, to the internal culture of the individual. I ceased to attach almost exclusive importance to the ordering of outward circumstances.”

I suppose an Effective Altruist could deflect Mill’s critique by saying: “We don’t attach exclusive importance to outward circumstances; we just try to make other-regarding efforts more effective. As long as Americans give just 2% of disposable income to charity, they are hardly at risk of neglecting themselves. They can cultivate their internal cultures all they want. We just help them to spend that 2% better.” And I think that’s fine–as far as it goes. I am just not sure it offers any hope of addressing the problems that keep me up at night, such as:

  • Corruption (writ large), meaning the capture of public goods for private profit.
  • Massive collective-action problems, especially global warming.
  • Hatreds of various kinds: religious, racial, national.
  • Discouragement about democracy and the potential to improve the world from the bottom-up.
  • The global shift to oligarchy.
  • Authoritarianism, especially of the macho, xenophobic, militaristic variety that unites Putin and Trump as well as many others.

See also: qualms about Behavioral Economics; qualms about a bond market for philanthropy; and why is oligarchy everywhere?

Job Opening at KIPCOR for Education & Training Director

We want to make sure our NCDD members on the job market check out the opening with the Kansas Institute for Peace & Conflict Resolution (KIPCOR) at Bethel College.

KIPCOR is accepting applications for a Director of Education and Training, and we are sure that the skills and backgrounds of many of our NCDD members would make a great fit for the position.

Here’s how KIPCOR describes the position:

Job Summary: This position is focused on the design, development, implementation and evaluation of all education and training courses, workshops, and educational programs offered by KIPCOR. However, it also includes some widely varied tasks that will incorporate research (potentially in the restorative justice field) and third-party intervention work in both interpersonal and group/organizational conflict. As with most small non-profit organizations, additional tasks related to social media management, scheduling logistics, networking, and miscellaneous office responsibilities will also be expected. Specific assignments will be made primarily from the Work Responsibilities section below, based on the education and expertise of the person holding this position.

This position will report to the director of KIPCOR, who will make specific job assignments. The successful applicant must be comfortable working with and advocating for an organization that focuses on peace, social justice, and conflict resolution. Additional information about KIPCOR may be found at www.kipcor.org.

You can read the full job announcement by clicking here. Good luck to all the applicants!

Pope Francis and the Struggle for Democracy

A thing to keep in mind during Pope Francis' visit this week: Ideas are sources of power. Definitions shape the frameworks we use to understand our experiences and the world around us. As Christopher Ansell shows in his recent book, Pragmatist Democracy, elites skillfully seek to control these definitions.

As the definition of democracy has shrunk, people have lost power. Every struggle for a more inclusive and equal society has been dramatically weakened. Coverage of the pope's visit, like coverage of the papacy since 2013, seems likely to emphasize Francis' values like compassion, inclusion, and service. But the coverage is also almost certain to slight any comments he makes on democratizing power.

The theme of civic power weaves through Francis' career. Long before he became pope, Jorge Bergoglio was developing such views. He ministered to the Iron Guard, a workers group for social justice. He worked in the slums of Buenos Aires. He fought skillfully against the repression of Argentinian dictators and strong men.

Francis was also influenced by the populist "theology of the people," emphasizing the wisdom of popular religious and cultural resources, as Jim Yardley reported in his New York Times article, "A Humble Pope, Challenging the World." In the face of vast economic inequality, Bergoglio came to see the danger of concentrations of power. "The pope is concerned that the plutocracy is destroying democracy," explained Sẚnchez Sonondo, chancellor of the Pontifical Academy of Sciences.

He expressed these views in a speech in Bolivia, July 9, 2015: "The future of humanity does not lie solely in the hands of great leaders, the great powers and the elites. It is fundamentally in the hands of peoples and in their ability to organize." In Laudato Si', the climate encyclical, the message is similar. "Public pressure has to be exerted in order to bring about decisive political action," he said. "Society through non-governmental organizations and intermediate groups must put pressure on governments...Unless citizens control political power -- national, regional, and municipal -- it will not be possible to control damage to the environment."

As Peter Levine pointed out on his civic engagement blog comparing coverage of Pope Francis with Barack Obama in the 2008 campaign, "The press completely ignores these leaders' talk of civic engagement. That theme was never covered in the 2008 presidential campaign, and no one mentions it when they cover the Pope."

Today democracy is narrowed to mean elections. As the US Agency for International Development site defines it, "Democracy refers to a civilian political system in which the legislative and chief executive offices are filled through regular competitive elections with universal suffrage." Recent academic literature shows the shrinkage, evident in the work of even as fine a scholar of democracy as Robert Putnam.

Putnam's first well-known book in 1993, Making Democracy Work, argued that successful government depends on public-spirited citizens and vital civic life. His new book, Our Kids, on inequalities, similarly marshaling enormous research, nonetheless shrinks democracy, which he defines "equal voice in government" as "the essence of democracy," without reference to civic culture.

For all their differences, both Republicans and Democrats in this year's election define democracy as elections. "We know what democracy is supposed to be about," said Bernie Sanders in his announcement speech. "It is one person, one vote, with every citizen having an equal say."

This week is an opportunity to connect Pope Francis to the concept of democracy as a "way of life," once widespread in America. The concept lived in the public work of settlers and immigrants who built schools, towns, local governments and local economies, what the historian Robert Wiebe called "portable democracy" in his book, Self-Rule.

It infused the land grant colleges of the 19th and 20th centuries, historically black colleges and universities, liberal arts colleges, and community colleges, which called themselves "democracy colleges."

The idea of democracy as a way of life also inspired the great democratic movements of our history including the black freedom movement of the 1950s and 1960s which shaped me as a college student.
The late Vincent Harding, Martin Luther King's friend who drafted his famous 1967 speech against the Vietnam War, described the larger conception of democracy in his book Hope and History.

Harding challenged the radical shrinking of the movement's meaning. "'Civil rights movement' is too narrow a description," Harding said. "In fact [the movement] was a powerful outcropping of the continuing struggle for the expansion of democracy...in which African-Americans have always been integrally engaged [and] in which we provided major leadership from the mid-1950s at least to the 1970s." The struggle for democracy "demonstrates the ways of human solidarity in the face of oppression, the common hope which empowers people everywhere, the deep yearning for a democratic experience that is far more than voting."

Harding also argued that democracy is not simply for the dispossessed. The democratic movement "searches for the best possibilities--rather than the worst tendencies - within us all."

Laudato Si' helps to illuminate the dynamics which have so eroded everyday "democratic experience," the replacement of civic and relational cultures with what he calls the "technocratic paradigm" across the sweep of modern societies. Schools, local businesses, colleges, clinics, nonprofits, even religious congregations have often turned into places where experts deliver services for clients and customers, losing their quality of free civic space. It is going to take a long march through settings of daily life to regrow civic muscle.

But as Ansell also observes, elite control over definitions "must contend with audiences who have power to arbitrate the use and meaning of concepts." If we pay attention to the pope's power messages as well as his value messages, it will help us launch this march, reawakening the larger meanings of democracy.

Pope Francis and the Struggle for Democracy

This week is an opportunity to connect Pope Francis to the concept of democracy as a "way of life," once widespread in America. The concept lived in the public work of settlers and immigrants who built schools, towns, local governments and local economies, what the historian Robert Wiebe called "portable democracy."

Pope Francis and the Struggle for Democracy

This week is an opportunity to connect Pope Francis to the concept of democracy as a "way of life," once widespread in America. The concept lived in the public work of settlers and immigrants who built schools, towns, local governments and local economies, what the historian Robert Wiebe called "portable democracy."

Theories of Deliberation

While deliberative theorists generally agree that, as John Dryzek writes, “democratic legitimacy resides in the right, ability, and opportunity of those subject to a collective decision to participate in deliberation about the content of that decision,” there continues to be much disagreement around exactly what constitutes ideal deliberation.

The word “deliberation” itself has multiple interpretations: Joshua Cohen argues that deliberation “focuses on debate on the common good.” Jane Mansbridge defines it as “mutual communication that involves weighing and reflecting on preferences, values and interests regarding matters of common concern.”

Regardless of the precise definition used, perhaps the more fruitful discussion is around what standards deliberation should be held to. That is, if we are to judge the health of a democracy by the quality of its deliberation, it begs the question: what constitutes high quality deliberation?

Earlier theorists such as Jürgen Habermas and John Rawls held what Mansbridge considers the “classical” model of deliberation, with an ideal of “deliberation to consensus on the common good.” This model, Mansbridge argues, “implied a relatively unitary conception of the common good, contested but discoverable through reason.”

Mansbridge sees modern theories of deliberation – “evolved” theories as she calls them – as better embracing pluralism of our diverse world. While she considers the classical ideal to rely on a collective discovery of the “common good,” she sees modern deliberation as still having value “when interests or values conflict irreconcilably.” In these cases “deliberation ideally ends not in consensus but in a clarification of conflict and a structuring of disagreement, which sets the stage for a decision by nondeliberative methods, such as aggregation through the vote.”

It’s not clear, though, that other deliberative scholars accept Mansbridge’s delineation between classical and evolved theories. Mansbridge considers Cohen, a student of Rawls, as a classical theorist though he himself might dispute the term.

While Cohen does continually consider deliberation as an exploration of the common good, he also plainly embraces pluralism, arguing: “A deliberative democracy is a pluralistic association. The members have diverse preferences, convictions and ideals concerning the conduct of their own lives. While sharing a commitment to the deliberative resolution of problems and of collective choices, they also have divergent aims, and do not think that some particular set of preferences, convictions or ideals is mandatory.”

Regardless of which theorists are “classical,” though, this divide raises important practical and theoretical questions about the nature of civil society and the ideal outcomes of deliberation.

While Cohen sees deliberation as a critical tool for shaping “the identity and interests of citizens in ways that contribute to the formation of a public conception of the common good,” theorists such as Mansbridge question whether a “common good” is attainable or even desirable.

This theoretical dispute, then, raises the more practical question – should deliberation culminate in a decision?

In what she sees as a break from “the definitions given by various other theorists,” Mansbridge intentionally leaves decision making out of her own definition, highlighting that “communities concerned with the quality of citizen participation seem to find deliberation an increasingly helpful concept in contexts unconnected with binding decisions.”

In contrast, Dryzek names “decisiveness” as one of the core elements of good deliberation, insisting that deliberation ought to be “consequential in influencing the content of collective decisions.” He does give a nod to non-decisive deliberation, pointing to worthwhile discussions in South Africa and Northern Ireland, and commenting that “deliberation also can play a part in healing.” 

Here to, though, Dryzek sees a certain type of decisiveness at play. “These exercises yield not consensus interpreted as universal agreement on a course of action and the reasons for it but rather an agreement to which all sides can reflectively assent—if for different reasons (including fear of what might otherwise happen),” he writes.

While not explicitly restricting his definition to include decision making, Dennis Thompson, on the other hand, does take a particular interest in “deliberation that leads directly to binding decisions.”

Thompson thoughtfully articulates why decision-making deliberation is special: “Structuring a discussion that in effect asks participants, ‘What do you, as an individual, prefer?’ begins to resemble the aggregative democracy (adding up the well-informed preferences of individuals) that deliberative democrats criticize. Discussions framed by asking participants, ‘What action should we, as a group, take?’ come closer to the deliberative democracy (creating a genuinely public opinion) that they favor.”

Cohen has a similar approach, defining deliberation in terms of its role within a democracy. He contrasts two approaches to democracy: the aggregative and deliberative. The aggregative conception requires “equal consideration for the interests of each member…along with a ‘presumption of personal autonomy’—the understanding that adult members are the best judges and most vigilant defenders of their own interests.”

Cohen, though, prefers the deliberative approach which has at its core “the idea that decisions about the exercise of state power are collective.” He goes on to add that the virtues of the deliberative view “are allied closely with its conception of binding collective choice.”

While reflecting deeper discussions about the nature of the common good in a pluralist society, this debate about decision-making surfaces another normative theory implicit in the deliberative literature: good deliberation has a positive effect not only on a community, but on individual participants.

This positive impact on the individual is inextricably linked to deliberation’s benefit to the community, and is often overshadowed by that broader narrative.

Both Thompson and Cohen articulate deliberation as a process of creating a shared understanding of the common good. People may enter deliberation with various beliefs, but they leave transformed, having co-created a shared understanding which had not existed prior to deliberation.

As Cohen says, “the relevant conceptions of the common good are not comprised simply of interests and preferences that are antecedent to deliberation. Instead, the interests, aims and ideals that comprise the common good are those that survive deliberation.”

Even Mansbridge seems to agree on these points, adding “epistemic value, or better knowledge” as the newest standard for good deliberation.

She sees communal epistemic value as being canonical to deliberation – which must, by her definition be “mutual” – but she leaves room for deliberation to be of directly value to the individual participants. “Although any mutual deliberation will include deliberation within the minds of the individuals involved,” she write, “the word mutual requires some two-way communication.”

Furthermore, Mansbridge has argued strongly for the inclusion of self-interest in deliberation – two elements which are classically considered to be in opposition. In a paper co-authored with some of today’s leading deliberative theorists (James Bohman, Simone Chambers, David Estlund, Andreas Føllesdal, Archon Fung, Cristina Lafont, Bernard Manin and José luis Martí), Mansbridge argues, “even in a deliberation aimed at consensus on the common good, the exploration and clarification of self-interests must play a role.”

Yet, the impact of deliberation on an individual is a vastly underexplored topic, as scholarship to date has focused largely on deliberation as a democratic process for collective decision-making.

facebooktwittergoogle_plusredditlinkedintumblrmail

Discover the Secrets of Successful Community Engagement

We are pleased to share the announcement below about a great workshop coming up this October 8 in Vancouver. NCDD Supporting Member Mark Pivon of Bang the Table shared this announcement via our great Submit-to-Blog Form. Do you have news you want to share with the NCDD network? Just click here to submit your news post for the NCDD Blog!


On October 8th, direct from Australia, Bang The Table’s CEO Matt Crozier, will deliver a free, fun and interactive workshop where he will reveal the Top Ten Best Practices of Community Engagement, distilled from thousands of events held by communities across Canada, and around the world.

Register here

Did you know, every week over 50 new consultations are launched using EngagementHQ? Over 140 organizations are currently engaging communities and stakeholders in important consultations this very moment. Organizations like The Canadian Department of the Environment, Alberta Energy Regulator, The City of Mississauga, The Regional Municipality of Halifax, The Vancouver Port Authority, The Vancouver Airport Authority, The Richmond School Board, The City of Richmond and dozens of others have chosen EngagementHQ and Budget Allocator from Bang The Table. What are they doing to ensure success? How are citizens responding?

These questions and more will be explored in our Vancouver EngagementHQ Roundtable.

Date: Thursday October 8th, 2015
Time: 7:30AM – 10:00AM
Location: SFU Morris J. Wosk Center for Dialog, 580 West Hastings Street, Salon B – ICBC Concourse

The registration desk will open at 7:30AM, and we will begin at 8:00AM sharp, so please be sure to arrive early.

Register here

What you can expect from attending this event:

  • Learn how to gather an unlimited number of ideas and enable your community to prioritize them in a democratic and transparent manner
  • Implement multi-channel communications strategies both offline and online to deliver consistency in messaging while securing the widest audience reach
  • Energize communities, build awareness, and secure consensus around important initiatives that eventually point to a record of accomplishment
  • Discover how to use social media in an effective and cross-collaborative manner
  • Mitigate risk and ensure compliance is upheld to all privacy standards while securing feedback from stakeholders, safely and securely
  • Gain insights from other practitioners in community and stakeholder engagement

Our demonstration and roundtable event is free and will provide the opportunity to review a variety of case studies, meet with fellow practitioners, and have your questions answered on online community and stakeholder engagement.

Hope to see you there. This event is free, but seating is limited. Please also note that attire is business casual.

Register here:
www.eventbrite.ca/e/discover-the-secrets-of-successful-community-engagement-tickets-18613955843